A philosophical grammar

The aim of these chapters is to isolate, and then to characterise further, a way of using nounphrases which has been called a uniquely referring or purely referential use. I will distinguish it from another sort of use or occurrence which is truly predicative of those and other expressions in a sent...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Main Author: Read, Stephen
Published: University of Oxford 1978
Subjects:
100
Online Access:http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.470126
id ndltd-bl.uk-oai-ethos.bl.uk-470126
record_format oai_dc
spelling ndltd-bl.uk-oai-ethos.bl.uk-4701262018-02-06T03:13:17ZA philosophical grammarRead, Stephen1978The aim of these chapters is to isolate, and then to characterise further, a way of using nounphrases which has been called a uniquely referring or purely referential use. I will distinguish it from another sort of use or occurrence which is truly predicative of those and other expressions in a sentence. Central to this distinction is a negation-argument of Frege's. Frege used it to distinguish quantified expressions from true names. I shall use it both to distinguish certain uses of expressions as names from their other uses as quantified phrases, and to find a logical form for quantified expressions. The latter application shows how Frege's claim that the quantifier in such a nounphrase belongs with the predicate means that quantified phrases are used predicatively. The argument is closely related to a point attributed to Geach, that predicates may be negated, while names cannot. I will suggest that the essential difference between quantified phrases and referring phrases is that the former are predicative, and may be negated. Then the latter, the referring uses, are not predicative. Indeed, they are in a sense semantically inert, or vacuous. They serve simply to provide an object for the truth-condition. It is this vacuity which renders them not subject to negation.100University of Oxfordhttp://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.470126https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:5fb32dfc-4cb1-4b66-9a29-933c10c5820bElectronic Thesis or Dissertation
collection NDLTD
sources NDLTD
topic 100
spellingShingle 100
Read, Stephen
A philosophical grammar
description The aim of these chapters is to isolate, and then to characterise further, a way of using nounphrases which has been called a uniquely referring or purely referential use. I will distinguish it from another sort of use or occurrence which is truly predicative of those and other expressions in a sentence. Central to this distinction is a negation-argument of Frege's. Frege used it to distinguish quantified expressions from true names. I shall use it both to distinguish certain uses of expressions as names from their other uses as quantified phrases, and to find a logical form for quantified expressions. The latter application shows how Frege's claim that the quantifier in such a nounphrase belongs with the predicate means that quantified phrases are used predicatively. The argument is closely related to a point attributed to Geach, that predicates may be negated, while names cannot. I will suggest that the essential difference between quantified phrases and referring phrases is that the former are predicative, and may be negated. Then the latter, the referring uses, are not predicative. Indeed, they are in a sense semantically inert, or vacuous. They serve simply to provide an object for the truth-condition. It is this vacuity which renders them not subject to negation.
author Read, Stephen
author_facet Read, Stephen
author_sort Read, Stephen
title A philosophical grammar
title_short A philosophical grammar
title_full A philosophical grammar
title_fullStr A philosophical grammar
title_full_unstemmed A philosophical grammar
title_sort philosophical grammar
publisher University of Oxford
publishDate 1978
url http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.470126
work_keys_str_mv AT readstephen aphilosophicalgrammar
AT readstephen philosophicalgrammar
_version_ 1718613600634929152