A Formal Approach to the Problem of Logical Non-Omniscience
We present the logical induction criterion for computable algorithms that assign probabilities to every logical statement in a given formal language, and refine those probabilities over time. The criterion is motivated by a series of stock trading analogies. Roughly speaking, each logical sentence p...
Main Authors: | , , , , |
---|---|
Format: | Article |
Language: | English |
Published: |
Open Publishing Association
2017-07-01
|
Series: | Electronic Proceedings in Theoretical Computer Science |
Online Access: | http://arxiv.org/pdf/1707.08747v1 |
id |
doaj-bdf8b0f110e04eeea3c9885377d48d78 |
---|---|
record_format |
Article |
spelling |
doaj-bdf8b0f110e04eeea3c9885377d48d782020-11-25T01:20:22ZengOpen Publishing AssociationElectronic Proceedings in Theoretical Computer Science2075-21802017-07-01251Proc. TARK 201722123510.4204/EPTCS.251.16:37A Formal Approach to the Problem of Logical Non-OmniscienceScott Garrabrant0Tsvi Benson-Tilsen1Andrew Critch2Nate Soares3Jessica Taylor4 Machine Intelligence Research Institute, Berkeley, CA Machine Intelligence Research Institute, Berkeley, CA Machine Intelligence Research Institute, Berkeley, CA Machine Intelligence Research Institute, Berkeley, CA Machine Intelligence Research Institute, Berkeley, CA We present the logical induction criterion for computable algorithms that assign probabilities to every logical statement in a given formal language, and refine those probabilities over time. The criterion is motivated by a series of stock trading analogies. Roughly speaking, each logical sentence phi is associated with a stock that is worth $1 per share if phi is true and nothing otherwise, and we interpret the belief-state of a logically uncertain reasoner as a set of market prices, where pt_N(phi)=50% means that on day N, shares of phi may be bought or sold from the reasoner for 50%. A market is then called a logical inductor if (very roughly) there is no polynomial-time computable trading strategy with finite risk tolerance that earns unbounded profits in that market over time. We then describe how this single criterion implies a number of desirable properties of bounded reasoners; for example, logical inductors outpace their underlying deductive process, perform universal empirical induction given enough time to think, and place strong trust in their own reasoning process.http://arxiv.org/pdf/1707.08747v1 |
collection |
DOAJ |
language |
English |
format |
Article |
sources |
DOAJ |
author |
Scott Garrabrant Tsvi Benson-Tilsen Andrew Critch Nate Soares Jessica Taylor |
spellingShingle |
Scott Garrabrant Tsvi Benson-Tilsen Andrew Critch Nate Soares Jessica Taylor A Formal Approach to the Problem of Logical Non-Omniscience Electronic Proceedings in Theoretical Computer Science |
author_facet |
Scott Garrabrant Tsvi Benson-Tilsen Andrew Critch Nate Soares Jessica Taylor |
author_sort |
Scott Garrabrant |
title |
A Formal Approach to the Problem of Logical Non-Omniscience |
title_short |
A Formal Approach to the Problem of Logical Non-Omniscience |
title_full |
A Formal Approach to the Problem of Logical Non-Omniscience |
title_fullStr |
A Formal Approach to the Problem of Logical Non-Omniscience |
title_full_unstemmed |
A Formal Approach to the Problem of Logical Non-Omniscience |
title_sort |
formal approach to the problem of logical non-omniscience |
publisher |
Open Publishing Association |
series |
Electronic Proceedings in Theoretical Computer Science |
issn |
2075-2180 |
publishDate |
2017-07-01 |
description |
We present the logical induction criterion for computable algorithms that assign probabilities to every logical statement in a given formal language, and refine those probabilities over time. The criterion is motivated by a series of stock trading analogies. Roughly speaking, each logical sentence phi is associated with a stock that is worth $1 per share if phi is true and nothing otherwise, and we interpret the belief-state of a logically uncertain reasoner as a set of market prices, where pt_N(phi)=50% means that on day N, shares of phi may be bought or sold from the reasoner for 50%. A market is then called a logical inductor if (very roughly) there is no polynomial-time computable trading strategy with finite risk tolerance that earns unbounded profits in that market over time. We then describe how this single criterion implies a number of desirable properties of bounded reasoners; for example, logical inductors outpace their underlying deductive process, perform universal empirical induction given enough time to think, and place strong trust in their own reasoning process. |
url |
http://arxiv.org/pdf/1707.08747v1 |
work_keys_str_mv |
AT scottgarrabrant aformalapproachtotheproblemoflogicalnonomniscience AT tsvibensontilsen aformalapproachtotheproblemoflogicalnonomniscience AT andrewcritch aformalapproachtotheproblemoflogicalnonomniscience AT natesoares aformalapproachtotheproblemoflogicalnonomniscience AT jessicataylor aformalapproachtotheproblemoflogicalnonomniscience AT scottgarrabrant formalapproachtotheproblemoflogicalnonomniscience AT tsvibensontilsen formalapproachtotheproblemoflogicalnonomniscience AT andrewcritch formalapproachtotheproblemoflogicalnonomniscience AT natesoares formalapproachtotheproblemoflogicalnonomniscience AT jessicataylor formalapproachtotheproblemoflogicalnonomniscience |
_version_ |
1725134703779905536 |